
Полная версия
On the Philosophy of Discovery, Chapters Historical and Critical
Quoted by Jebb, Pref. to Op. Maj.
83
Mosheim, Hist. iii. 161.
84
Op. Maj. p. 57.
85
Mosheim, iii. 161.
86
Gratian published the Decretals in the twelfth century; and the Canon and Civil Law became a regular study in the universities soon afterwards.
87
Tenneman, ix. 4.
88
Tenneman, ix. 25.
89
"Jam nobis manifestum est terram istam in veritate moveri," &c.—De Doctâ Ignorantiâ, lib. ii. c. xii.
90
De Doct. Ignor. lib. i. c. i.
91
De Conjecturis, lib. i. c. iii. iv.
92
Born in 1433.
93
Born 1529, died 1597.
94
Aristoteles Exotericus, p. 50.
95
Tiraboschi, t. vii. pt. ii. p. 411.
96
"Franciscus Patricius, novam veram integram de universis conditurus philosophiam, sequentia uti verissima prænuntiare est ausus. Prænunciata ordine persecutus, divinis oraculis, geometricis rationibus, clarissimisque experimentis comprobavit.
Ante primum nihil,Post primum omnia,A principio omnia," &c.His other works are Panaugia, Pancosmia, Dissertations Peripateticæ.
97
Tiraboschi, t. vii. pt. ii. p. 411.
98
Dissert. Perip. t. ii. lib. v. sub fin.
99
Tenneman, ix. 148.
100
Tenneman, ix. 167.
101
Ibid. 158.
102
Agrippa, De Occult. Phil. lib. i. c. l.
103
Written in 1526.
104
Philip Aurelius Theophrastus Bombastus von Hohenheim, also called Paracelsus Eremita, born at Einsiedlen in Switzerland, in 1493.
105
Hist. Sc. Id. b. ix. c. 2. sect. 1. The Mystical School of Biology.
106
Tenneman, ix. 221.
107
Tenneman, ix. 265.
108
Bernardini Telesii Consentini De Rerum Natura juxta propria Principia.
109
I take this account from Tenneman: this Proem was omitted in subsequent editions of Telesius, and is not in the one which I have consulted. Tenneman, Gesch. d. Phil. ix. 280.
110
Proem.
111
"De Principiis atque Originibus secundum fabulas Cupidinis et Cœli: sive Parmenidis et Telesii et præcipuè Democriti Philosophia tractata in Fabula de Cupidine."
112
"Talia sunt qualia possunt esse ea quæ ab intellectu sibi permisso, nec ab experimentis continenter et gradatim sublevato, profecta videntur."
113
Thom. Campanella de Libris propriis, as quoted in Tenneman, ix. 291.
114
Economisti Italiani, t. i. p. xxxiii.
115
Tenneman, ix. 305.
116
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xvi. c. iii. sect. 2.
117
Ibid. b. xvii. c. ii. sect. 1.
118
Quæst. Peripat. i. 1.
119
Tenneman, ix. 108.
120
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. v. c. iii. sect. 2.
121
Tenneman, ix. 420. "Quæcunque ab Aristotele dicta essent commenticia esse." Freigius, Vita Petri Rami, p. 10.
122
Rami, Animadv. Aristot. i. iv.
123
See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. iv. c. iv. sect. 4.
124
Tenneman, ix. 230.
125
Ibid. 108.
126
Tenneman, ix. 246.
127
Melancthon, De Anima, p. 207, quoted in Tenneman, ix. 121.
128
His works have never been published, and exist in manuscript in the library of the Institute at Paris. Some extracts were published by Venturi, Essai sur les Ouvrages de Leonard da Vinci. Paris, 1797.
129
Leonardo died in 1520, at the age of 78.
130
Paul III. in 1543.
131
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. v. c. ii.
132
Born 1537, died 1619.
133
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xvii. c. ii. sect. 1.
134
Fabricius, De Motu Locali, p. 182.
135
p. 199.
136
Speculationum Liber, p. 195.
137
Ibid. p. 169.
138
Gulielmi Gilberti, Colcestriensis, Medici Londinensis, De Magnete, Magneticisque Corporibus, et de Magno Magnete Tellure, Physiologia Nova, plurimis et Argumentis et Experimentis demonstrata.
139
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xii. c. i.
140
Pref.
141
De Magnete, lib. vi. c. 3, 4.
142
Nov. Org. b. i.
143
B. i. Aph. 64.
144
Vol. ix. 185.
145
De Magnete, p. 60.
146
B. iii. c. 4.
147
Nov. Org. b. ii. Aph. 48.
148
Drinkwater's Life of Galileo, p. 18.
149
Life of Galileo, p. 9.
150
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. ii. sect. 5.
151
Life of Galileo, p. 29.
152
Ibid. p. 33.
153
Il Saggiatore, ii. 247.
154
Il Saggiatore, ii. 200.
155
Ibid. i. 501.
156
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. ii. sect. 2.
157
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. ii. sect. 4.
158
Ibid. b. v. c. iv. sect. 1.
159
De Stell. Mart. p. iv. c. 51 (1609); Drinkwater's Kepler, p. 33.
160
Published 1604. Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ix. c. ii.
161
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. v. c. iv. sect. i.
162
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vii. c. vi. sect 1.
163
De Stell. Mart. p. 11. c. 19.
164
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ii. c. iv. sect. 6.
165
Ibid. sect. 8.
166
Montucla, i. 566.
167
De Augm. lib. iv. c. 1.
168
And in other passages: thus, "Ego enim buccinator tantum pugnam non ineo." Nov. Org. lib. iv. c. i.
169
Lib. 1. Aphor. 78 et seq.
170
Aug. Sc. Lib. iii. c. 4. p. 194. So in other places, as Nov. Org. i. Aph. 104. "De scientiis tum demum bene sperandum est quando per scalam veram et per gradus continuos, et non intermissos aut hiulcos a particularibus ascendetur ad axiomata minora, et deinde ad media, alia aliis superiora, et postremo demum ad generalissima."
171
Nov. Org. 1. Aph. 22.
172
Ib. Aph. 20.
173
1 Ax. 15.
174
Nov. Org. lib. ii. Aph. 19.
175
Inst. Mag. par. iii. (vol. viii. p. 244).
176
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. x. c. i.
177
Ib. c. iv.
178
Nov. Org. lib. i. Aph. 61.
179
Nov. Org. lib. ii. Aph. 10.
180
Aph. 11.
181
Aph. 15, p. 105.
182
Page 110.
183
Herschel, On the Study of Nat. Phil. Art. 192.
184
Nov. Org. lib. i. Aph. 40.
185
Nov. Org. lib. i. Ax. 103.
186
Edinb. Rev. No. cxxxii. p. 65.
187
Ib.
188
Pref. to the Nat. Hist. i. 243.
189
Nov. Org. lib. i. Aph. 19.
190
Ibid. lib. i. Aph. 20.
191
Aph. 27.
192
Ib. 28.
193
Aph. 104. So Aph. 105. "In constituendo axiomate forma inductionis alia quam adhuc in usu fuit excogitanda est," &c.
194
Ep. ad P. Fulgentium. Op. x. 330.
195
Nov. Org. i. Aph. 113.
196
See the motto to Kant's Kritik der Reinen Vernunft.
197
Œuvres Philosophiques de Bacon, &c. par M. N. Bouillet, 3 Tomes.
Examen de la Philosophie de Bacon (Œuvres Posthumes du Comte J. de Maistre).
Bacon, sa Vie, son Temps, sa Philosophie, par Charles de Remusat.
Histoire de la Vie et des Ouvrages de François Bacon, par J. B. de Vaugelles.
Franz Baco von Verulam, von Kuno Fischer.
The Works of Francis Bacon, collected and edited by James Spedding, Robert Leslie Ellis, and Douglas Denon Heath.
198
Note to Aph. xviii.
199
Pref. to the Parasceue, Vol. i. p. 382.
200
Anatomical Exercitations concerning the Generation of Living Creatures, 1653. Preface.
201
He used similar expressions in conversation. George Ent, who edited his Generation of Animals, visited him, "at that time residing not far from the city; and found him very intent upon the perscrutation of nature's works, and with a countenance as cheerful, as mind unperturbed; Democritus-like, chiefly searching into the cause of natural things." In the course of conversation the writer said, "It hath always been your choice about the secrets of Nature, to consult Nature herself." "'Tis true," replied he; "and I have constantly been of opinion that from thence we might acquire not only the knowledge of those less considerable secrets of Nature, but even a certain admiration of that Supreme Essence, the Creator. And though I have ever been ready to acknowledge, that many things have been discovered by learned men of former times; yet do I still believe that the number of those which remain yet concealed in the darkness of impervestigable Nature is much greater. Nay, I cannot forbear to wonder, and sometimes smile at those, who persuade themselves, that all things were so consummately and absolutely delivered by Aristotle, Galen, or some other great name, as that nothing was left to the superaddition of any that succeeded."
202
Lib. i. c. 2, 3.
203
Anal. Post. ii.
204
Pars iii. p. 45.
205
See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. ii.
206
Cap. i. ii.
207
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ix. c. ii.
208
Meteorum, c. viii. p. 187.
209
Mackintosh, Dissertation on Ethical Science.
210
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vii. c. i.
211
Castelli, Torricelli, Viviani, Baliani, Gassendi, Mersenne, Borelli, Cavalleri.
212
De Plenitudine Mundi, in qua defenditur Cartesiana Philosophia contra sententias Francisci Baconi, Th. Hobbii et Sethi Wardi.
213
Bacon's Works, vol. ii. 111.
214
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vii. c. i.
215
Nov. Org. lib. ii. Aph. 2.
216
Ib. lib. ii. Aph. 45.
217
Optics, qu. 31, near the end.
218
Qu. 28.
219
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. v. and b. vii.
220
Optics, qu. 31.
221
History of Ideas, b. iii. c. x.
222
Ibid. b. iii. c. ix. x. xi.
223
Opticks, qu. 31.
224
Nov. Org. l. ii. Aph. 2. "Licet enim in natura nihil existet præter corpora individua, edentia actus puros individuos ex lege; in doctrinis tamen illa ipsa lex, ejusque inquisitio, et inventio, et explicatio, pro fundamento est tam ad sciendum quam ad operandum. Eam autem legem, ejusque paragraphos, formarum nomine intelligimus; præsertim cum hoc vocabulum invaluerit, et familiariter occurrat."
Aph. 17. "Eadem res est forma calidi vel forma luminis, et lex calidi aut lex luminis."
225
Essay, b. xi. c. iv. sect. 3.
226
Ibid. c. xiii. sect. 22.
227
History of Ideas, b. iii. c. iii. Modern Opinions respecting the Idea of Cause.
228
Ibid. b. i. c. iv.
229
Langue des Calculs, p. 1.
230
Grammaire, p. xxxvi.
231
Since the selection and construction of terms is thus a matter of so much consequence in the formation of science, it is proper that systematic rules, founded upon sound principles, should be laid down for the performance of this operation. Some such rules are accordingly suggested in b. iv. of the Nov. Org. Ren.
232
Disc. Prélim. p. viii.
233
Helvetius Sur l'Homme, c. xxiii.
234
P. xiii.
235
See Mr.Sharpe's Essays.
236
Price's Essays, p. 16.
237
P. 18.
238
Reid, Essays on the Powers of the Human Mind, iii. 31.
239
Stewart, Outlines of Moral Phil. p. 138.
240
Whately, Polit. Econ. p. 76.
241
Cousin, Fragmens Philosophiques, i. 53.
242
Ibid. i. 67.
243
See also the vigorous critique of Locke's Essay, by Lemaistre, Soirées de St. Petersbourg.
244
Ampère, Essai, p. 210.
245
Kritik der Reinen Vernunft, Pref. p. xv.
246
The sensational system never acquired in Germany the ascendancy which it obtained in England and France; but I am compelled here to pass over the history of philosophy in Germany, except so far as it affects ourselves.
247
i. p. 14.
248
i. p. 7.
249
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xi. c. vii.
250
P. 15.
251
P. 16.
252
M. Comte's statement is so entirely at variance with the fact that I must quote it here. (Phil. Pos. vol. i. p. 705.)
"Le second théorème général de dynamique consiste dans le célèbre et important principe des aires, dont le première idée est due à Kepler, qui découvrit et démontra forte simplement cette propriété pour le cas du mouvement d'une molecule unique, ou en d'autres terms, d'un corps dont tous les points se meuvent identiquement. Kepler établit, par les considérations les plus élémentaires, qui si la force accélératrice totale dont une molecule est animée tend constamment vers un point fixé, le rayon vecteur du mobile décrit autour de ce point des aires égales en temps egaux, de telle sorte que l'aire décrite au bout d'un temps quelconque croît proportionellement à ce temps. Il fit voir en outre que réciproquement, si une semblable relation a été vérifiée dans le mouvement d'un corps par rapport à un certain point, c'est une preuve suffisante de l'action sur le corps d'un force dirigée sans cesse vers ce point."
There is not a trace of the above propositions in the work De Stellâ Martis, which contains Kepler's discovery of his law, nor, I am convinced, in any other of Kepler's works. He is everywhere constant to his conceptions of the magnetic virtue residing in the sun, by means of which the sun, revolving on his axis, carries the planets round with him. M. Comte's statement so exactly expresses Newton's propositions, that one is led to suspect some extraordinary mistake, by which what should have been said of the one was transferred to the other.
253
Vol. ii. p. 433.
254
Vol. ii. 640.
255
I venture to offer this problem;—to express the laws of the phenomena of diffraction without the hypothesis of undulations;—as a challenge to any one who holds such hypothesis to be unphilosophical.
256
ii. p. 641.
257
ii. p. 673.
258
Hist. Ind. Sc. ii. 489, b. x. c. i.
259
ii. p. 561.
260
i. 50.
261
i. 41.
262
ii. 433.
263
Phil. Pos. ii. 392-398.
264
[A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, being a connected view of the Principles of Evidence, and of the Methods of Scientific Investigation. By John Stuart Mill.]
265
These Remarks were published in 1849, under the title Of Induction, with especial reference to Mr. J. S. Mill's System of Logic.
266
My references are throughout (except when otherwise expressed) to the volume and the page of Mr. Mill's first edition of his Logic.
267
On this subject see an Essay On the Transformation of Hypotheses, given in the Appendix.
268
B. vii. c. iii. sect. 3.
269
B. iii. c. ix. art. 7.
270
B. i. c. iii.
271
B. iii. c. viii.
272
Discourse, Art. 192.
273
B. xi. c. xi.
274
Phil. b. xiii. c. ix. art. 7.
275
B. xiii. c. viii.
276
Given also in the Phil. Ind. Sc. b. xiii. c. vii. sect. 17.
277
Ibid. b. vi. c. iv.
278
See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xii. note D, in the second edition.
279
There are some points in my doctrines on the subject of the Classificatory Sciences to which Mr. Mill objects, (ii. 314, &c.), but there is nothing which I think it necessary to remark here, except one point. After speaking of Classification of organized beings in general, Mr. Mill notices (ii. 321) as an additional subject, the arrangement of natural groups into a Natural Series; and he says, that "all who have attempted a theory of natural arrangement, including among the rest Mr. Whewell, have stopped short of this: all except M. Comte." On this I have to observe, that I stopped short of, or rather passed by, the doctrine of a Series of organized beings, because I thought it bad and narrow philosophy: and that I sufficiently indicated that I did this. In the History (b. xvi. c. vi.) I have spoken of the doctrine of Circular Progression propounded by Mr. Macleay, and have said, "so far as this view negatives a mere linear progression in nature, which would place each genus in contact with the preceding and succeeding ones, and so far as it requires us to attend to the more varied and ramified resemblances, there can be no doubt that it is supported by the result of all the attempts to form natural systems." And with regard to the difference between Cuvier and M. de Blainville, to which Mr. Mill refers (ii. 321), I certainly cannot think that M. Comte's suffrage can add any weight to the opinion of either of those great naturalists.
280
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. x. note (VA) in the second edition.
281
B. xi. c. v. art. 11.
282
I have given elsewhere (see last chapter) reasons why I cannot assign to M. Comte's Philosophie Positive any great value as a contribution to the philosophy of science. In this judgment I conceive that I am supported by the best philosophers of our time. M. Comte owes, I think, much of the notice which has been given to him to his including, as Mr. Mill does, the science of society and of human nature in his scheme, and to his boldness in dealing with these. He appears to have been received with deference as a mathematician: but Sir John Herschel has shown that a supposed astronomical discovery of his is a mere assumption. I conceive that I have shown that his representation of the history of science is erroneous, both in its details and in its generalities. His distinction of the three stages of sciences, the theological, metaphysical, and positive, is not at all supported by the facts of scientific history. Real discoveries always involve what he calls metaphysics; and the doctrine of final causes in physiology, the main element of science which can properly be called theological, is retained at the end, as well as the beginning of the science, by all except a peculiar school.
283
I have also, in the same place, given the Inductive Pyramid for the science of Optics. These Pyramids are necessarily inverted in their form, in order that, in reading in the ordinary way, we may proceed to the vertex. Phil. Ind. Sc. b. xi. c. vi.
284
Cosmos, vol. ii. note 35.
285
The reader will probably recollect that as Induction means the inference of general propositions from particular cases, Deduction means the inference by the application of general propositions to particular cases, and by combining such applications; as when from the most general principles of Geometry or of Mechanics, we prove some less general theorem; for instance, the number of the possible regular solids, or the principle of vis viva.
286
B. vi. c. v.
287
c. vi.
288
Hist. b. vi. c. vi. sect. 13.
289
Hist. Ind. Sc. b. viii.
290
Reprinted in the Appendix to this volume.
291
Phil. Pos. t. iv. p. 264.
292
Logic, b. vi. c. 3.
293
Jones, On Rent, 1833.
294
Literary Remains, 1859.
295
The substance of this and the next chapter was printed as a communication to the Cambridge Phil. Soc. in 1840.
296
Or in the earlier editions, in the Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences.